A Critical Review : Post-Colonial Critics on Liberal Feminism
By : Raditya Putranti Darningtyas
Department of International Relations
Department of International Relations
Universitas
Gadjah Mada
Gender and Politics
Midterm Assignment
Gender and Politics
Midterm Assignment
______________________________________________________________________________
INTRODUCTION
During
the past few decades, feminist theory with its multiple branches has attempted
massive deconstruction and attacks against several established notions in
social science including order in society, ideology, and culture. At the heart
of these attacks lay protest against distribution of power that have, by
tradition, favored men at the expense of women. From the furious assertion that
rape and other type of sexual harassment should not be tolerated as mere
consequences of unfortunate episode, to the complex theories of postmodernism
that discards the very concept of differences as inherently oppressive, these
protests have provoked many challenges to all traditional conception of order
as inherently androcentric. At its first emergence in the 19th and
early 20th century, first wave feminism mainly focused on gaining
political rights for women although some other also campaigned for sexual and
reproductive rights. The suffragettes and suffragists were campaigning for
women’s votes, demanding equal contract, marriage, parenting and property
rights for women. However, many weaknesses have presented itself within Liberal
Feminism framework that leads this strand of feminism to its failure in
accommodating the interest of intersectional women in their endeavor toward
equality. Several others also criticized Liberal Feminism as European centric
and too white centric, neglecting the oppressive natures of inherited
power-knowledge relationship within the creation of feminist theories. This
critical review will examine several critics of Liberal Feminism and identify
the common threads that tie these authors together as post-colonialist feminist
theorists.
SUMMARY
Liberal Feminism
Liberal
feminism held important role in 1960s and 70s women’s liberation movement in
western countries like United States and Britain although it had also been expressed
much earlier by writers such as Marry Wollstonecraft in Vindication of the Rights of Woman.[1] Liberals
hold a view of human nature which stresses the capacity of human beings for
rational thoughts. It is this capability to reason and rationalize which gives
rise to the ideas that human beings have innate rights. Liberals support the right of individuals to seek
fulfillment and pursue their own interest providing that in doing so they
respect other’s rights.[2] Rights
were often denied to women on the ground that they are ‘irrational’ beings so
making them less than fully human. The argument that women naturally differ
from men was used to justify unequal treatment to women. Feminist at that time
then argued for women’s equality on the grounds that women, like men, were
rational beings capable of making their own decision and determining their own
best interest. During that time, feminist used what were essentially liberal
arguments to challenge the unequal treatment presented to women.
Wollstonecraft
also argued that the realization of genuine equality entailed the provision of
equal access to education and economic opportunity for women. Women
historically had been confined to domestic service in their own home, limiting
their opportunity in exercising their intellectual abilities or developing
other skills unrelated to domestic works. Liberal feminism is particularly driven
by emancipatory vision to highlight inequalities faced by women, and address
these through legal and political reform.[3]
Liberal feminist writing, therefore, draws attention to the various forms of
oppression which women around the world are subject to, and seeks change
through the removal of legal obstacles to gender equality.[4]
The liberal feminist normative vision of the emancipation of women is thus one
which is assumed to be both possible and universally applicable[5],
making liberal feminist scholarship and liberal feminist activism are closely
related to each other.
Post-Colonial Feminism
Postcolonialists
argue that western academia, while making it as if disinterested in
imperialism, conspires in perpetuating racist structures and relations.[6]
Although the question of who or what is “postcolonial” is an increasingly
complex one with the existence of cross-border migration, “postcolonial” may
refer to men and women from various backgrounds.[7] While
rejecting the “narrative of the oppressed” which has dominated western writing
on the subaltern,[8]
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak argues that western scholars, who neglect
non-western subjects, avoid their responsibility to the disempowered. The main
goal of post-colonialism is facilitating progression past the legacy of
colonialism and it offers variety of strategies in achieving this. One of them
involves the opening of space for the disenfranchised ‘other’ to speak. Other
historian Chakrabarty challenges Eurocentric view of history by highlighting
the way European historical texts continue to be glorified as the foundations
of modern political thoughts, while non-European texts are seen as historical
relics.[9] This
dominant Eurocentric historical narratives support racist power structures by
measuring the progress of other cultures in terms of their “distance” from
Western modernity. This includes liberal feminist theories that is developed
under European hegemony and written in the perspective of the colonizer,
neglecting the existence of other narratives in the colonized world. Post
Colonialist Feminism then emerged mainly to criticize the Eurocentric nature of
liberal feminism.
ANALYSIS OF ARGUMENTS
One
of the main criticisms to have arisen from post-colonial writers is that the
appropriation of women of color’s experiences by liberal feminist writers, and
therefore by the liberal feminist movement in what is called as “discursive
colonization”.[10]
There are several examples that were used by post-colonial writers in their
work; Ania Loomba focuses on paternalistic patterns amongst westerners writing
about Indian women that have carried over from the imperial age[11],
while Valerie Amos and Pratibha Parmar criticizes the way cross-cultural
studies employ black women’s experiences for “exotic comparison”.[12]
However, post-colonial writers come to an agreement that when authentic
experiences of women of color are featured in the work of liberal feminist, it
is not for their benefit.[13]
When
we take a look deeper within this discursive colonization, there is a problem
of misrepresentation of women of color that tends to be portrayed as monolithic
and as victims.[14]
Most liberal feminist wrote about women of color by homogenizing the
experiences of vast groups of women, vaguely categorizing them as “Women of the
Middle East” or “Women of Africa” in poor methodologies. Radcliffe accuses this
approach as erasing stories of those who resist oppression. The narratives of “Third
World Women” portray women of color as victims as well as the privileged
recipient of first world concern.[15]
This also includes the exclusion of women with diverse identity from mainstream
feminist discourse. This exclusion severely undermines the self-representation
by postcolonial women because of potential inaccuracy of someone else’s account
and the problem of women of color who must constantly highlight their
exclusion, rather than being able to fully participate in liberal feminist
discourse.[16]
Another
criticism of liberal feminism has something to do with the inability of western
authors to recognize that oppression of women may differ according to class,
race, religion and ethnicity. The liberal feminist normative vision of the
emancipation of women is one which is assumed to be both possible and
universally applicable.[17]
This problem emerges from the essentialist claim that female oppression is
universal.[18]
Women of color must create what is
called as “schizophrenic split” in themselves between their identity as a woman
and their race or ethnicity in order to relate to the liberal feminist
ideology.[19]
Moreover, this “white egocentricity” as mentioned by Spelman[20]
leads to misunderstanding of the kind of liberation that is being sought after
by women of color. The massive generalization
of women’s experience by liberal feminist writers has undermined many aspects
unique to the experience of women who don’t relate with the experience of white
females living in a developed country. Racism and sexism are not separate forms
of oppression for women of color thus making the statement, “we are all women”
insufficient in most cases.[21]
The last thread which has arisen from
many postcolonial critics is related to the lack of awareness of the impact
that a theory has on those who are theorized about.[22] Critical
theorist, Robert Cox, notably wrote that “theory is always for someone and for
some purpose”[23]
He establishes an important relationship between theory and theorist by arguing
that a theory can never be objective. In liberal feminist writings there is a
lack of self-consciousness about the ability of academic circles in
discouraging women’s movements in third world countries.[24] The
western biased found in liberal feminism often times directly clashing with
non-western values, leading liberal feminism to its failure in gaining support
from women in non-western countries because people simply see feminism as
another form of western imposition. For example, liberal feminist theory often
disregards Islamic teachings as oppressive religion and regard Moslem women as
its victims. This may translates into reckless condemnation of hijab and other
religious practices deemed sacred by its believers. This condemnation is seen
as an attack toward the sanctity of Islam by most of Moslem women and resulting
in them rejecting feminism altogether. The rejection of feminism from
non-western women becomes a loss for not only liberal feminist activist but
also feminism as a whole, making the needs to provide specific empowerment for
specific identity of women more urgent if feminism both as an ideology and
movement still wants to thrive in gaining more supporters.
WORKS CITED
Cox,
R. (1981). Social Forces, States and World Order. Millennium. Vol. 10, No. 2.
Fuss,
D. (1989). Essentially Speaking: Feminism, Nature and Difference. London,
Routledge.
Hutchings,
K. (2007). Feminist Ethics and Political Violence. International Politics. Vol.
44
Lugones,
M. and Spelman, E. (1983). Have we got a theory for you! Feminist theory,
cultural imperialism and the demand for “the woman’s voice”. Women’s Studies
International Forum. Vol. 6, No. 6.
Mohanram
(1999). Black Body: Women, Colonialism and Space. Minneapolis, University of
Minnesota Press
Mohanty,
C. (1988). Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses.
Feminist Review. No. 30.
Radcliffe,
S. (1994). (Representing) Post-Colonial Women: Authority, Difference and
Feminisms. Area. Vol. 26, No. 1.
Spelman, E. (2006). Gender & Race: The Ampersand Problem in Feminist Thought. In: Morgan, S. ed. The Feminist History Reader. Oxon, Routledge. pp. 273-283.
Spivak, G. (1988). Can the Subaltern Speak? In: Nelson, C. and Grossberg, L. ed., Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. Basingstoke, Macmillan Education.
Spivak, G. (1999). A Critique of Postcolonial Reason: Toward a History of the Vanishing Present. Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press.
Steans, Jill. (1998). Gender and International Relations: An Introduction. Oxford, Polity Press
Tickner, J. A. and Sjoberg, L. (2007). Feminism. In: Dunne, T. et al eds. International Relations Theories. Oxford, Oxford University Press
Tickner, J. A. and Sjoberg, L. (2007). Feminism. In: Dunne, T. et al eds. International Relations Theories. Oxford, Oxford University Press
Tong,
R. (1998). Feminist Thought: A More Comprehensive Introduction. Oxford,
Westview Press
[1]
Tong 1998: 15-23.
[2]
Steans 1998 : 16
[3] Tickner
and Sjoberg 2007 : 188
[4]
Ibid, p. 188
[5]
Hutchings 2007 : 92-93
[6] Spivak
1999 : 208
[7]
Mohanram 1999: 179
[8]
Spivak 1988 : 61
[9]
Ibid 1999 : 5-6
[10]
Mohanty 1988 : 61
[11]
Mohanty 2006 : 315
[12]
Ibid 2006 : 287
[13]
Radcliffe 1994 : 28
[14]
Mohanty 1988 : 65-66, Radcliffe 1994 : 26,
Spivak,1988 : 84
[15]
Radcliffe 1994 : 26
[16]
Ibid 1994 : 27
[17]
Hutchings 2007 : 92-93
[18]
Fuss 1989 : 2
[19]
Lugones and Spelman 1983 : 576
[20]
Spelman 2006 : 274
[21]
Ibid 2006 : 277-278
[22]
Lugones and Spelman 1983 : 579, Mohanty 1988
: 62; Spivak, 1988, p. 91)
[23]
Cox 1981 : 128
Comments
Post a Comment